Any views expressed within media held on this service are those of the contributors, should not be taken as approved or endorsed by the University, and do not necessarily reflect the views of the University in respect of any particular issue.

Liam McLaughlin

Liam McLaughlin

Politics, Philosophy and Economics student at the University of Edinburgh

Draft of: Realists, Nationalism, & inter-state violence: gaps in explaining conflict initiation

Realists, Nationalism, & inter-state violence: gaps in explaining conflict initiation

An enduring debate within Nationalism studies is centred between Primordialists, who maintain that nations are distinct natural historical political units (Smith 1986), and Modernists, who argue that nations are “imagined communities” created by group relations between individuals (Anderson 1983, pp.6). Though most contemporary Nationalism scholars are firmly Modernists, IR Realists are distinct in that their theoretical canon takes premises from aspects of both traditions. They tacitly accept the Primordialist ontological position that nations/states (through an affiliation to nation-states) are independent natural entities in the world – that creates a ‘Nationalism’ as a tool of self-preservation (Waltz 1959). But, simultaneously they accept the Modernist view that Nationalism, through an aggregation of individual’s actions, engenders the “motion” of inter-state dynamics – through public opinion affecting geopolitical realities (Measrsheimer 2014). Thus, IR Nationalism’s roots as a conceptual object is represented twice in Realist theory – once from the primordialists at the purely macro level and once from the modernist at the micro level. This tension is most apparent in Realist theory’s ommision of explaining how Nationalism as a ‘Modernist’ causal force, leads to inter-state violence that takes place in the ontologically ‘Primodialist’ inter-state arena (Van Evera 1994; Cederman 2002). More simply, here I ask if Realists can form a unified theory of Nationalism that can coherently explain the relationship, if any, between Nationalism and the initiation of interstate conflict?

Here I examine four approaches to fill this explanatory gap: a “Traditional view” that Nationalism has an inherent propensity towards inter-state violence; a top-down “Structural approach” associated with Structural Realists; a bottom-up “Individualist approach” from Human-Nature Realism; and the nacent “Social Psychology” empirical approach. I find that no current approach adequately bridges the explanatory gap between the Modernist and Primodialist interpretations of the effects of Nationalism on initation of the interstate conflict; however, developments within Social Psychology and Individualist approaches appear most promising to bridge this gap.

Nationalism, first being studied as a method of state-formation, has always been associated with violence through the sentiment that “states make war and war makes states” (Tilly 1990, pp.32). Indeed, historically this link goes back atleast to Tolstoy’s arguement that “to destroy war, [we must first] destroy patriotism” (Tolstoy 1896). This link between war and nationalism enshirines the “Traditional view” of nationalist inter-state violence initiation where Nationalism is defined merely as a state’s propensity to engage in inter-state conflict (Kosterman & Feshbach 1989) and research continues to defend this definitional relationship (Woodwell 2007; Pavković 2000; Lieven 2004; Gagnon 1994). However, this is unhelpful in answering our question as it forces us to ‘beg the question’ when explaining the causal relationship between interstate-violence and Nationalism by appealing to the definition of Nationalism as a propensity towards violence when explaining why instances of violence occur. Thus, assuming the conclusion and so, beyond establishing a correlation, these cannot provide adequate theoretical explanations of conflict intiation.

In contrast, the “Structural approach” attributes the primary cause of inter-state violence to the structure of the international system. Structuralists maintain that Nationalism contributes to violence by creating instability in the international system. Nationalism, they maintain, causes breakdowns of stable security dilemma, by either ‘capturing’ states to follow through on their Militaristic rhetoric that had been needed to fuel defence spending (Snyder 1991), or by giving actors overconfidence in their own state’s power leading to miscalculations of their peer-competitors’ relative strength (Johnson 2009; Debs 2020). However, there is reluctance to overcomplicate the structural model by making Nationalism an endogenous factor[1]. Instead, Structural Realists approximate accurate explanations of Nationalism by making event-driven alterations to their models[2]. Consequently, their models become a reflection of the events they considered (Legro and Moravcsik 1999). Contemporary Structural Realists primarily focus on Nationalism in the Chinese context, motivated by politically salient fears of changing world polarity and rising-power conflicts (Feng & He 2020). For example, Mearsheimer’s (2014) focuses on an aggressive ‘hyper-nationalism’ outcompeting patriotism in China and Shirk’s (2008) warnings of jingoism in the Chinese public and military being left unchecked by the political leadership. As a result the Structural approach is somewhat narrow: it provides a good explanation of Nationalism and inter-state violence in the Chinese context, but does not give more universally applicable explanations. However, this approach will likely improve from new event-driven considerations of the Russo-Ukrainian conflict – necessitating Nationalism specific theoretical extenstion that increase the explanatory power of structural realist approaches[3].

A related Nationalism-specific “Structural approach” attempts to re-define Nationalism to fit as an endogenous variable within Structural Realist models. These theorists take a Bismarckian view of Nationalism as a tool mobilised by self-interested political elites who engender nationalistic seniments within a state’s population (Hearn 2006)[4]. This perspective originates within historical thinkers like Mandeville (1724) or Rousseau’s (1762) ‘State Religion’. Contemporary IR theorists such as Snyder (2000) and Schrock-Jacobson (2012) have adopted the Bismarkian top-down view and, through empirical studies, confirm that Nationalism plays a role in the initiation of inter-state violence. Under this treatment, however, Nationalism is not an independent causal factor of interstate-violence but only a predictive symptom of violence, which instead originates from elites who mobilise popular support in preparation for war. Instead, causality falls to state elites, which – in so far as state elite’s interest corresponds with ‘state’ interests from the Structural Realist perspective – create a complete model that explains the correlation between Nationalism and inter-state violence.

Yet, this latter structuralist group’s contributions remain contested as they seemingly give too great a causal role for state elites in Nationalist mobilisation, which Ko (2022) shows play a statistically insignificant role in mobilizing ‘othering’ nationalist sentiment in China. Indeed, Weiss (2014) and Reilly (2013) argue that more globally elites tend to curtail populist Nationalist mobilisation from fear that Nationalist public pressure could snowball and restrict their policy choices. So, it appears we cannot simplify Nationalism to purely an instrument of statecraft. Consequenly, it is prudent that in absence of vindicating empirical evidence, Nationalism must remain exogenous to Structural Realist models. Nevertheless, Schrock-Jacobson (2012) remains a foundational paper for the later Social Psychology approach for her considerations that Nationalism is not a monolith but has multiple distinct effects that are specific to the method of Nationalist mobilisation.

Contrastingly, the “Individualist approach”, instead derives its methodology from Waltz’s “first-image” Human-Nature Realism and attempts to build up an explanatory theory of Nationalism from assumptions about the nature of Nationalistic individuals (Waltz 1959). These assume that Nationalists favour the state using violent means to achieve its national interests (Bertoli 2017; Gruffydd-Jones 2017) and then explain how individual propensities aggregate to create state preferences. However, because Nationalist pressure is likely to play out differently in insulated authoritarian theocracies than in parliamentary democracies, this approach leads to a form of Realist Institutionalism whereby scholars explain how the architecture of state structures leads to differing outcomes. These create quite sophisticated models of specific state systems, for example, Gries et al (2016) and Weiss & Dafoe (2019) in China or Drezner (2008) in the USA.

However, Human-Nature Realism has been challenged from a growing empirical “Social Psychology” approach, which argues Realist assumptions about Nationalism are too simplistic. Following from Schrock-Jacobson (2012), this approach divides Nationalism into context and method specific effects. Using survey data & controlled experiments they find that revanchism (Lickel 2012) and fear of losing national prestige (Schatz, Staub, & Lavine 1999) play a role in conflict prone behaviours. Recent studies from Chung (2015) and Ko (2022) have developed the role of Nationalism and policy preference in China; Ko determining that Nationalism can affect individuals’ preferences for conflict-prone policies, positively or negatively, dependent on whether Nationalist sentiment is outward-looking (creating resentment against another country) or inward-looking (creating self-assuring feelings of national security).

Yet, Social Psychologists refrain from generalising these findings, due to apparent gaps in their understanding of IR theory. For example, Ko (2022) makes small interpretive faults in her understanding of the security dilemma by appealing to answers on “what do you think likelihood of war will be?” to show that Nationalist Military parades does not change how individuals’ interpretate of their state’s security dilemma, rather than “what do you think likelihood of winning a war will be?” which fits better with Realist security-dilemma theory. This difficulty is compounded by the widespread use of Lambert et al.’s (2010) laboratory test method, which use leading questions to “stimulate” nationalist sensibilities in preparation for experiments, however, these “stimulating” questions are often not vetted for cretaing an adverse biasing effect. Thus, researchers may not be “stimulating” Nationalism in the way we would expect in a real-world setting – giving the study’s conclusions questionable external validity. Consequently, there appears a need for further field experiments. Further, future research should attempt to disentangle Nationalism’s effect from current hostile state-level relationships by studying states that now co-exist within mutual-defence/aid associations (European Union/EEA or NATO), but whose state Nationalism has been traditionally defined against a belligerent national “significant other” (Triandafyllidou 1998, pp. 593) such as in France-Germany, UK-Ireland, or Turkey-Greece.

Finally, it appears that more robust Social Psychology studies into Nationalism’s effect on Individual’s policy preferences, which are then applied to Realist Institutional models, will have the most success in explaining the role of Nationalism on inter-state violence. Considering a wider range of Nationalist contexts in both the Structural and micro-level approaches would give conclusions with greater explanatory power. However, we should not discount growing attention from the Social Psychology approach and the probable response of event-driven Structural Realists to the Russo-Ukrainian conflict as routes to progress Realist theories closer to a satisfactory explanation of Nationalism and inter-state conflict intitation.

 

Bibliography

Anderson, B. (1983). Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism. New York, NY: Verso.

Bertoli, A. (2017). “Nationalism and Conflict: Lessons from International Sports.”, International Studies Quarterly. Vol. 61, No. 4, pp. 835–49.

Cederman, L. (2002). “Nationalism and Ethnicity.” In Handbook of International Relations, ed. Carlsnaes, W. Risse, T. Simmons, B. pp. 409-428. London: SAGE.

Chung, E. (2015). “Can Affirming National Identity Increase International Trust? Experimental Evidence from South Korean, Chinese, and Japanese Nationals.” Asian International Studies Review. Vol. 16, No. 1, pp 75–97.

Debs, A. (2020). “Mutual Optimism and War, and the Strategic Tensions of July Crisis.” American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 66, No 2. pp 271–84.

Drezner, D. (2008). “The Realist Tradition in American Public Opinion”, Perspectives on Politics, Vol. 6, No. 1, pp. 51-70.

Edinger, H. (2022). “Offensive ideas: structural realism, classical realism and Putin’s war on Ukraine”, International Affairs, iiac217. [doi: 10.1093/ia/iiac217]

Feng, H. He, Kai. (2022). China’s Challenges and International Order Transition: Beyond “Thucydides’s Trap”. Ann Arbor, MICH: University of Michigan Press.

Gagnon, V. P. (1994). “Ethnic Nationalism and International Conflict: the case of Serbia”, International Security, Vol 19. No 3. Pp. 130-166.

Gallagher, A. (1989). “Social Identity and the Northern Ireland Conflict”, The Tavistock Institute, Vol. 42, No. 10. [Doi: /10.1177/001872678904201004]

Gries, P. Steiger, D. Wang, T. (2016). “Popular Nationalism and China’s Japan Policy: The Diaoyu Islands Protests, 2012–2013.” Journal of Contemporary China, Vol. 25, No. 98, pp. 264–276.

Gruffydd-Jones, J. (2017). “Dangerous Days: The Impact of Nationalism on Interstate Conflict.” Security Studies. Vol. 26, No. 4, pp. 698–728.

Hearn, J. (2006). Rethinking Nationalism: A Critical Introduction. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University press.

Johnson, D. (2009). Overconfidence and War. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Ko, J. (2022). “Not So Dangerous? Nationalism and Foreign Policy Preference”. International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 66, No. 3, pp. sqac053.

Kosterman, R. Feshbach, S. (1989). “Toward a Measure of Patriotic and Nationalistic Attitudes.” Political Psychology, Vol. 10, No. 2, pp. 257–274.

Lambert, A. Scherer, L. Schott, J. Olson, R. Andrews, R. O’Brien, T. Zisser, A. (2010). “Rally Effects, Threat, and Attitude Change: An Integrative Approach to Understanding the Role of Emotion.”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 98, No. 6, pp. 886–903.

Legro, J. Moravcsik, A. (1999). “Is anybody still a Realist?”, International Security, Vol. 24, No. 2, pp. 5-55.

Lickel, B. (2012). “Retribution and Revenge.” In The Oxford Handbook of Intergroup Conflict, ed. by Tropp, L. pp. 89–105. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lieven, A. (2004). America Right or Wrong: An Anatomy of American Nationalism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Mandeville, B. (1724). The Fable of The Bees: or, Private Vices, Publick Benefits. Vol 2. (Republished 1988). Indianapolis, IND: Liberty Fund.

Mearsheimer, J. (2014). The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. The Updated Edition. New York, NY: W.W. Norton.

Moxon-Browne, E. (1983). “National Identity in Northern Ireland”. In Social Attitudes in Northern Ireland: The First Report. Ed Stringer, P. Robinson, G. Belfast: Blackstaff press.

Palan, Ronen. (1991). “Misguided Nationalism: The Causes and Prospects for Slovenian Independence”, The Contemporary Review, Vol. 259, No. 1058, pp. 119-127.

Pavković, A. (2000). The fragmentation of Yugoslavia: Nationalism and War in the Balkans. 2nd ed. New York, NY: St. Martin’s Press.

Reilly, J. (2013). Strong Society, Smart State: The Rise of Public Opinion in China’s Japan Policy. New York: Columbia University Press.

Rousseau, J. (1762). On the Social Contract; or, Principles of Political Right. (Republished 1895). London: George Allen & Unwin.

Schatz Robert T., Staub Ervin, Lavine Howard. 1999. “On the Varieties of National Attachment: Blind versus Constructive Patriotism.” Political Psychology. Vol. 20, No. 1, pp. 151–74.

Schrock-Jacobson, G. (2012). “The Violent Consequences of the Nation: Nationalism and the Initiation of Interstate War”, The Journal of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 56, No. 5, pp. 825-852.

Shirk, S. (2008). China: Fragile Superpower. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Smith, A. (1986). The ethnic origins of nations. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons.

Snyder, J. (1991). Myths of Empire: Domestic Politics and International Ambition. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Snyder, J. (2000). From Voting to Violence: Democratization and Nationalist Conflict. New York, NY: W.W. Norton.

Tilly, C. (1990). Coercion, Capital, and European States, AD 990–1992. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.

Tolstoy, L. (1896). Patriotism, or Peace?, Available at: https://www.marxists.org/archive/tolstoy/1896/patriotism-or-peace.html

Triandafyllidou, A. (1998). “National Identity and the ‘Other’.” Ethnic and Racial Studies. Vol. 21, No. 4, pp. 593–612.

Van Evera, S. (1994). “Hypotheses on Nationalism and War”. International Security. Vol. 18, No. 4, pp. 5-39.

Waltz, K. (1959). Man, the State, and War: a theoretical analysis. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

Waltz, K. (2003). Conversations with History: Kenneth Waltz. UC Berkley’s conversations with history presentation series by Harry Kreisler for the University of California. June 2003. [Available at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=F9eV5gPlPZg ]

Weiss, J. (2014). Powerful Patriots: Nationalist Protest in China’s Foreign Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Weiss, J. Dafoe, A. (2019). “Authoritarian Audiences, Rhetoric, and Propaganda in International Crises: Evidence from China.” International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 63, No 4, pp. 963–973.

Woodwell, D. (2007). Nationalism in International Relations: Norms, Foreign Policy and Enmity. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.

[1] See Waltz (2003) discussing Realist model simplicity.

[2] Similar dynamics exist in sub-state nationalism studies focusing on competing identities from 1980s Northern Ireland (Moxon-Browne 1983; Gallagher 1989), later emphasising state-collapse from 1990s Yugoslavia (Palan 1991).

[3] For example, Edinger (2022).

[4] Other modernists make similar claims but do not exclude considering Nationalism as a bottom-up constructivist/individualist force, Anderson (1983).

Share

Leave a reply

You may use these HTML tags and attributes: <a href="" title=""> <abbr title=""> <acronym title=""> <b> <blockquote cite=""> <cite> <code> <del datetime=""> <em> <i> <q cite=""> <s> <strike> <strong>

css.php

Report this page

To report inappropriate content on this page, please use the form below. Upon receiving your report, we will be in touch as per the Take Down Policy of the service.

Please note that personal data collected through this form is used and stored for the purposes of processing this report and communication with you.

If you are unable to report a concern about content via this form please contact the Service Owner.

Please enter an email address you wish to be contacted on. Please describe the unacceptable content in sufficient detail to allow us to locate it, and why you consider it to be unacceptable.
By submitting this report, you accept that it is accurate and that fraudulent or nuisance complaints may result in action by the University.

  Cancel